22 Comments

In a sense you R.H. are following the ends justify the means principle. If you have a nouble cause we should all rally behind you. As opposed to never lie or never discriminate no matter what.

Expand full comment

Take this with a salt cellar, since I am no expert, but:Isn't empirical science about predicting REAL behaviors of objects, rather than how they "should" work?Therefore, if people usually do not make rational choices when dealing with resources, labor, and etc, why should an economist waste time acting like what they do is rational? A model based on rationality of people disagrees with reality, and therefore, cannot predict anything useful about the economy or its workings.

Expand full comment

Strange7person:

So when a heir billionaire uses Google to look up something pointless, Google adds more value to the economy as whole than when a poor student uses Google to study?

Value to you personally is not value to 'economy as whole'. I'm not sure latter even means anything.

Furthermore if I know that the google's cost of providing the service is $0.001 , I can refuse to pay any more than, say, $0.002 even though I may lose more than $0.002 from inability to google (fortunately a lot of other people act the same, forcing price down). How much people are willing to pay is not a measure of anything other than how much people are willing to pay.

Expand full comment

If google charged $10 per search and you were using it anyway (and sane), that would mean each search was worth at least $10 to you. If the marginal cost to them of providing the service was negligibly low, they would be adding at least $10 of value to the economy as a whole for every such transaction.

Expand full comment

Crap! his the post button instead of the keyboard. Damn tablet!

Anyway, Robin doesn't appear to say that his intangible concern for biased discrimination is a limited quantity. Rather it seems he's fairly clear that he apportions his time, efforts and other finite resources according to his utilitarian principles.

I, for my part, would like to know how he integrates that with pursuits that may not have any immediate payoff, but which could be tremendously beneficial to society as a whole in the long run. For example, as a physicist, I’m keenly aware of how much of the mathematics underpinning my discipline was discovered long before its practical utility was even remotely apparent. Had mathematicians not devised those tools, they may not have been laying around ready when it was their time to advance other disciplines. More to the point, many are obscure enough that they may not have been apparent to physicists and other scientists if there weren’t mathematicians just down the hall to help them find the antique maths they needed. More broadly, so much of our tool-designing civilization is built on chains of discoveries that are themselves not nearly as useful for any brass tacks applications, that I wonder at the wisdom of apportioning resources on a strict calculus of immediate benefits.

Expand full comment

It goes without saying that I could be wrong, but I think some people are misreading Robin's original post.

Expand full comment

So you are saying that for any discrimination-type, endeavor-type pair, you have only a fixed amount of sympathy to give and you apportion it according to the broad utility of the endeavor-type, ignoring the discrimination-type.

I still think boundary cases are important. I also want you to address the issue of a large number of people suffering, but where suffering is totally located only to that group without spillover effects. Also, what if discrimination-type issues can be contagious from one endeavor-type to another, more impactful endeavor-types? For example, if you assume you are working in a legal framework that heavily uses precedents as a means to decide important new debates, then getting discrimination-type issues right is hugely important regardless of their immediate endeavor-type impacts, because later discrimination situations will be judge by precedent rather than by how much the discrimination holds up progress.

Expand full comment

If a car salesman is facing bias because he's a car salesman—I might be less inclined to think well of his quest to dissolve that bias. This inclination would accord with how much I think people being biased towards believing "car salesmen are scandalous" reflects the reality of being a car salesman (which, at some reality:bias ratio, stops the belief from being a "bias").

On the other hand, if a car salesman is facing some type of gender bias, race bias, attractiveness bias, w/e—I see no reason why I should care less of said bias because of his profession. Consider it a, "I might not agree with what you say, but I will fight to the death for your right to say it," type philosophy. My beliefs in the detriments of gender bias are independent of my beliefs of a car salesman.

This seems very much related to the idea of ad hominem. In regards to my sympathy towards a situation, I don't see any justification in relating someone's profession to what irrational beliefs they're the target of. In fact, I actively think that accepting biases based on who they're directed towards is a bad, bad process of thought.

Don't get me wrong. I understand *why* people think like this—and I understand that it's a common thing that clicks off in the mind without second thought (i.e. - Any of the many situation where some injustice is ok because of who it was directed towards.) Though I think anyone who knows they think this way should work to not think this way. 

The more I think about it, the more I feel I may be misunderstanding the post—I think it strange you don't look to be discouraging this type of mindset (assuming my interpretation is correct).

Expand full comment

The amount of value-to-you that Google creates is the maximum amount you'd pay for Google searches if they had no competitors and were charging you money.

That's just ridiculous, Yudkowsky. Google doesn't add  $10 of value for you for every $10 you pay; you're not considering the value you parted with. That value corresponds to the value of what you would otherwise spend $10 on.

Expand full comment

In the standard supply & demand theory, the *marginal* value of each good equals the marginal cost. Most actual values will be higher, and most actual costs will be lower. But since it is the marginal values and costs that says if there are too many or too few of each thing, they are the focus of policy. But when there are market failures, such as is caused by signaling effects, the marginal private value (or cost) can differ a lot from the marginal social value (or cost).

Expand full comment

What?  That sounds like total economic nonsense to me.  The amount of value you capture doesn't necessarily have anything to do with the amount of value you create.  The amount of value-to-you that Google creates is the maximum amount you'd pay for Google searches if they had no competitors and were charging you money.  Since Google does have competitors, they have low negotiating power and are only able to capture a tiny fraction of the value they create for you.  Craigslist creates huge amounts of economic value - causes many trades to take place that wouldn't take place otherwise - and captures almost none of it.

A used car seller *might theoretically* have almost no social value, if they pay prices for cars so low that nobody buys a car who otherwise wouldn't on grounds of being able to sell it used, charge prices high enough that almost nobody buys a car who wouldn't have gotten one otherwise, capture almost all of the value of the trade for themselves, and so basically generate no surplus for others while removing labor from the economy that might otherwise be productive.  The fact that they were making money would not contradict this.(Robin, standard economists know about this, right?  I ask because your own reply doesn't refer to it.)

Expand full comment

You might have noticed that I talk a lot about signaling on this blog. Signaling creates a predictable understandable difference between the private value of doing something and its social value. 

Expand full comment

The whole point of economics is to show what rational agents would do.

No, the "whole point" of economics is to model the economic system to predict economic phenomena. It's supposed to be an empirical science, not a branch of game theory. Economists, it turns out, tend to believe that the assumption of rationality works, even when it doesn't.

Expand full comment

The whole point of economics is to show what rational agents would do.  Once we're talking about biases, it's not economics proper.  Instead, it's 'behavioral economics', a field in psychology that some  economists like.

Expand full comment

I was saying what *I* care most about.

What's not clear is why anyone else should care. I'd guess it follows (roughly) from your utilitarianism. Then, why not argue it that way?

There are potentially glaring contradictions with utilitarianism, and (despite my being a moral antirealist (http://tinyurl.com/7dcbt7y), I think I might find utilitarianism more compelling than your personal values. What if the persecuted group is large and suffers intensely but its misfortune doesn't harm anyone else? Here, a bit of deontology seems to creep into your utilitarianism.

Expand full comment

Couple of points..

First, I think Robert made clear in the first sentence that he was dealing with a hypothetical that he didn't necessarily agree with.  Second, doesn't the "pricing theory of value" assume that you're dealing with an unencumbered price mechanism?  One could certainly, then, have distorted prices in a mixed economy such as the one we live in.

Expand full comment